5 myths about learning and innateness

5 myths about learning and innateness

Recent exchanges I have had on Twitter lead me to believe that each of these risible myths is alive and well, even here in late 2022; let me assure you that they all are nonsense.  For once I will spare you links to the guilty.

Suffice to say that none follows logically. Regardless of what the empirical facts are for biology, it should be obvious even from the armchair that onecouldin principle believe, e.g., in both the existence of innatenessandlearning.

And in fact, literallyeveryoneI know does. None of the myths relate to positions that anyone in the real world holds. For example, I am not aware of anybody who believes in innateness and yetdeniesthat learning is important.  Certainly all the outspoken nativists I know (Chomsky, Pinker, Spelke, Gallistel, myself, the late Jerry Fodor, etc) are all perfectly happy to recognize that some sorts of learning take place, even as we all also think that some important part of human mental machinery is built-in, in sense of naturally arising via the processes of developmental biology, independently of specific experience.

Take Chomsky, often characterized as the ultimate arch nativist. Chomsky’s argument for a Language Acquisition Device is, actually, on close inspection, an argument for (a specialized)learning mechanism. Chomsky’s LADis not mind you, simple stimulus-response-reinforcement, deep reinforcement learning, or back-propagation, or anything else currently fashionable, but it is still a form of learning in whichvarious parameters of a child’s mind are set in specific ways, based on data.

Now Chomsky’s notion of learning may, perhaps, be more like a newborn chick’s imprinting than Skinnerian conditioning, but it is still learning just the same, setting parameters based on data. That’s what learning is, tuning parameters to data, and even Chomsky thinks we do some of that. (He thinks just happens to think that innate constraints play in role in the process that tunes the parameters.)

Likewise, Fodor’s argument inThe Language of Thoughtthat concepts must be acquired through some sort of innate primitives and innate combinatorial apparatus doesn’t deny learning. It just holds that whatever concepts are acquired-which is to say learned—are learned via application of the aforementioned combinatorial apparatus.

Pinker’s theory of semantic bootstrapping, likewise, is in part a theory of how some modest bits innate knowledge about language universals might allow a child to fill in—learn—the rest. Spelke’s Core Knowledge theory is a theory about how Core Knowledge bootstraps other knowledge, and so on. Gallistel is as nativist as they come, and wrote a whole book calledThe Organization of Learning.

In fact, the more you like learning, themoreyou should embrace innateness, because part of what you should be embracing is what Peter Marler calledinnately-guided learning,a rubric that describes each of theories I just discussed.The more of that you have, the more you can probably learn.

A beautiful example of innately-guided learning is the “Garcia effect”, otherwise known as learned taste aversion. Taste something, and get sick soon afterwards, and you will avoid that taste for a very long time. The neural mechanisms for that represent aninnate, domain-specific adaptation for learninga very specific type of information. (The imprinting of a chick on its best nearby candidate for mother is another well-known case).

My own guess, based on my reading of the ever-controversial psychology literature, is that humans are likely innately endowed withmanylearning mechanisms, each with different properties. Some might possibly be tailored to language, others for observational learning, classical conditioning, hypothesis testing, cost-benefit analysis, and so on, perhaps dynamically combined and recombined in various ways in real time. The very variety of innate learning mechanisms may be central to what makes us humans special.

In case it is not obvious, I am a card carrying nativist, as enamored with innateness as I am with learning. All of my work, on child language acquisition, generalization in neural networks, my book on developmental biology, etc, have really been about both: about trying to understand how biology (or in the case of machines, prior knowledge) and learning work together.

Why am I into both learningandinnateness? In large partbecauseI care about what make humans unique. In keeping with the above, the answer almost surely lies with some set of (not-yet -understood) but learning mechanisms that are themselves innate. As Terrace and Pettito and others discovered empirically, if you raise a chimp among humans, but you don’t get a human mind. Chimps lack the correct learning mechanisms; they can’t transform linguistic input into human-level understanding. If chimps and humans were born with the same learning mechanisms, you would expect to find more convergence between them than we actually observe. (Yes, their brains are smaller, but human children have smaller brains than adults, yet outperform the adults at learning language. Size may be part of it it, but size isn’t everything. What counts is what you do with the neural material you have.) Knowing more about exactly what it is beyond size that makes our mind unique would tell us an immense amount, both about ourselves, and about how we might want to build our AI.

Not wishing to belabor that which ought to be obvious, I leave countering the remaining myths as an exercise for the reader to work out. I trust that they are not challenging to refute. (The trickiest is the idea that if you are nativist you necessarily have to believe in innate, domain-specific knowledge; hint: you don’t. To join the club all you have to do is to think that some nontrivial stuff is innate. My own guess: we have a rich mixture of many innate mechanisms, some domain-specific, some domain-general.)

I only raise all this because so many people periodically forget a fundamental fact: learning and innateness are not and need not be mortal enemies.

Except for advanced learning mechanisms that are themselves learned (like the value of spaced practice, or ways of analyzing a book, eg starting from a perusal of the table of contents), most learning mechanisms themselves probably are innate.

If you believe in learning, you ought believe that your learning mechanisms come fromsomewhere.On pain of infinite regress, at least one of those learning mechanisms must be innate. So unless you believe in magic, you are already, like it or not, a nativist.

Good news for those who find any of the above upsetting: You can always redefine your problems away! For example, you can maximally narrow the definition ofinformationand argue that DNA doesn’t contain information (somebody actually tried to tell me this a few days ago) or that DNA contains no information about phenotypes (somebody else tried to tell me this the next day). Alternatively, you can take a maximally broad definition oflearningand include under that umbrella literally anything that might be innate by dint of evolution, and call that learning too! (Honestly, someone last week tried to tell me that the structure of the hand was learned; I am not making this stuff up!)

But wait, that’s not all. You can also broaden the termempiricismto include every possible process, and narrow the termnativismto only include literal neural blueprints for entire brains. Or even do both at once! Narrow nativism AND broaden empiricism, and you are guaranteed to have everything line up on your side of the argument!Schopenhauer couldn’t have said it better.

Images Powered by Shutterstock